During the 1990s, although the market paradigm was dominant in economics and public policy, a new literature stressing the importance of the role of the state in industrialization rose to fame. We can mention (1989), (1990) or (1995). This literature dwelled on the East Asian miraculous industrialization and showed with empirical and historical evidence how the state apparatus was necessary to spark the economic take off. More recently, these academic attempts multiplied (for instance in the developmental state literature with , 2002) and gained new interest after the 2008 financial crisis. Yet, this literature is not novel and draws its inspiration from previous economists and social scientists, who for a long time warned us of the danger of disintegrating the state from the economic sphere. On the other hand, mainstream theorists tend to undermine, if not ignore, state intervention and consider it as an exogenous variable to economic growth (see for example , , and ). The post-1980s era had provoked academic debates around the role of the market versus the role of the state for developing countries: the claim made by mainstream economists and politicians was that countries which pursued a state-led industrial policy failed greatly and that the was an illustration of this (see for example the ). On the contrary, it was observed that the East Asian newly industrialized countries (the so-called 鈥榝our tigers鈥) 鈥榤iraculously鈥 developed by pursuing market-oriented policies (see for example ). As heterodox economists, such as Amsden, Wade, and Evans, retaliated by stating the exact opposite, the extent to which the state could be an industrial actor or not become a new agora for both camps.
However, what if the terms of the debate were problematic at the conceptual level from the beginning? Is the dichotomy 鈥渟tate vs. market鈥 as evident as it appears to be in policy debates? A theoretical detour going back to Karl Polanyi might help us shed some light on this issue.
In his famous book (1944), Karl Polanyi proposed a theory of industrialization embedded in human institutions. Polanyi鈥檚 thesis was pretty radical, although a truism in itself: 鈥極ur thesis is that the idea of a self-adjusting market implied a stark utopia鈥. And by market economy, Polanyi means: 鈥榓n economic system controlled, regulated and directed by market prices鈥 (p.71).
The 19th century was the age of liberalism and the laissez-faire doctrine was the directing principle in economic policy (initiated by the British abolition of the corn laws in 1846). The sole path to industrialization was to trust market forces, at least in theory (see ). Indeed, three major elements are necessary to the industry: land, labor and capital. These were treated as commodities that needed a market mechanism to be distributed in the most efficient way. As a consequence, industrial policy excluded state intervention or planning in the three markets. Yet, the conceptual implications of this doctrine are very problematic: are these three commodities, real commodities that could be subjected to market mechanism? What is the anthropological tissue behind the industrial process? Polanyi was mainly concerned with this issue and tried to unearth the metaphysical grammar of the liberal doxa by enquiring on the nature of these commodities and on the nature of the market process. His argument goes as follows:
a) Capitalism and industrialization mechanisms rely on three commodities: labor, land and capital.
b) A commodity is an object that is produced to be sold in the market.
c) Labor is an aggregate term to signify human laborers, land is in fact nature itself and capital is a purchasing power through a banking and monetary system that is not produced.
d) Humans, nature and money are not a production for market sales and purchases.
e) Therefore labor, land and capital are fictitious commodities.
The conclusion (e) of the argument leads to Polanyi鈥檚 main critique: implementing a market economy for these three commodities means the total destruction of society. Since these commodities are fictitious and are in essence what constitutes a society, their fate cannot be rendered to the unique market prices. Rather, the state acts as a preserver and protector of society and industrial policy falls into this role. As Polanyi expresses it: 鈥楾he protection of society, in the first instance, falls to the rulers, who can directly enforce their will鈥 (p. 174). Namely, the state/bureaucracy leads policies to protect/develop society (indeed, the nature of the bureaucracy and political system makes implementing effective 鈥榩rotection鈥 problematic. We will deal with this issue later on). Here we can have an interpretation of Polanyi鈥檚 view of protection related to the normative definition of development as a process that broadens and expands individual social choices (perhaps the idea of protection here implies more a focus on negative freedoms- namely, freedom from 鈥搑ather than an attention on positive freedoms. The latter is what Sen refers to most of the time in his . Indeed a clear distinction between both freedoms is conceptually problematic as as a triadic relation shows. Yet, the idea of protection in Polanyi鈥檚 corpus of concepts also implies a social security system that empowers individuals鈥 capabilities).
As a matter of fact, society is not a homogenous ensemble and although it has a structure, it also has classes with different and opposite interests that render the implementation of industrial policy very problematic. Polanyi acknowledged this problem. Furthermore, an international monetary system embodied by institutions such as the IMF, the World Bank and the WTO, where bargaining power is a major issue, industrial policy, and government intervention in general, becomes contentious (see or , for example). Polanyi published his book in 1944 and could not forecast the upcoming neoliberal era in the 1980s.
Nonetheless, the reference to Polanyi鈥檚 work enlightens us in questioning the frontiers between the market and the state. As to planning being opposed to a market-oriented economy, Polanyi remarkably argued that: 鈥榳hile laissez-faire economy was the product of deliberate state action, subsequent restrictions on laissez-faire started in a spontaneous way. Laissez-faire was planned; planning was not鈥 (p.147). In fact, the market itself requires a plan as well as planning, but the 19th century liberals did not plan to implement a planning economy. Hence, although planning is ubiquitous in the economic sphere, its idiosyncratic meaning remains distinct from a market mechanism in the literature.
Mohamed Obaidy is an MS student in Economics at The New School
Excellent !
LikeLiked by 1 person
Reblogged this on .
LikeLiked by 1 person
A very good glimpse of why an institutionalist approach and class analysis are key to understanding soceity and the economy.
LikeLiked by 1 person
[…] This blog was first published on 黑料社区. […]
LikeLike
[…] The Market or the State: Why Polanyi Still Matters (Mohamed Obaidy, The New School) […]
LikeLike